Sunday, December 16, 2018
Saturday, December 15, 2018
Recognize this practice for what it is
I've basically been arguing here for a decade now that there can be two coherent theories on deaccessioning.
You can think it's always wrong -- that museums hold their works in the public trust, for the benefit of present and future generations, and they should never be sold.
Or you can think works can, on occasion, be sold, if there is a sufficient reason. That reason can be to acquire other work. Or it can be something else (e.g., to keep from going out of business). You have to look closely at each individual case and decide. (This is my view.)
It's the middle view -- the view of the Deaccession Police, the view of the AAMD, the conventional wisdom in the field -- that is, frankly, ridiculous. It holds that deaccessioning is deeply unethical and a violation of the public trust if the proceeds of sale are used for Purpose X (anything other than buying art) … but completely fine if the proceeds are used for Purpose Y (buying art). I've never understood how that could be at all persuasive to anyone.
Former museum director Steven Miller has a piece in The New Criterion coming at it largely from the first perspective, and calling out "the obvious hypocrisy of voicing concern for the survival of collections, only to sell them into oblivion":
"Though it is largely accepted within the profession, deaccessioning is still a controversial issue. The debate surrounding it surfaces with alarming frequency. For the most part, however, complaints are rarely directed at the practice itself, but at what happens if any profits realized from the sale of the museum collections are 'misused.' Furor tends to erupt only when income will cover operating expenses or capital and debt payments, rather than pay for future acquisitions. Oddly, controversy about commercial deaccessioning sidesteps the fact that, unless the purchase is made by another museum, objects will probably be lost to the public forever. How does that practice align with the preservation imperative museums repeatedly embrace …? Put simply: it does not."
He adds that once a work is sold, "we might as well have tossed them on a bonfire. This is a total abrogation of museological duty."
What's his answer? First, "recognize this practice for what it is and acknowledge that it contradicts a museum's commitment to preserving and caring for its collections." And then he ends up signing on to the Ellis Rule:
"Correcting the unfortunate results of unbridled commercial deaccessioning is simple. An item can be deaccessioned and kept by the museum for educational purposes. Or it can be sold or given to another museum. Everyone wins in this situation …. One museum's loss can always be another's gain."
You can think it's always wrong -- that museums hold their works in the public trust, for the benefit of present and future generations, and they should never be sold.
Or you can think works can, on occasion, be sold, if there is a sufficient reason. That reason can be to acquire other work. Or it can be something else (e.g., to keep from going out of business). You have to look closely at each individual case and decide. (This is my view.)
It's the middle view -- the view of the Deaccession Police, the view of the AAMD, the conventional wisdom in the field -- that is, frankly, ridiculous. It holds that deaccessioning is deeply unethical and a violation of the public trust if the proceeds of sale are used for Purpose X (anything other than buying art) … but completely fine if the proceeds are used for Purpose Y (buying art). I've never understood how that could be at all persuasive to anyone.
Former museum director Steven Miller has a piece in The New Criterion coming at it largely from the first perspective, and calling out "the obvious hypocrisy of voicing concern for the survival of collections, only to sell them into oblivion":
"Though it is largely accepted within the profession, deaccessioning is still a controversial issue. The debate surrounding it surfaces with alarming frequency. For the most part, however, complaints are rarely directed at the practice itself, but at what happens if any profits realized from the sale of the museum collections are 'misused.' Furor tends to erupt only when income will cover operating expenses or capital and debt payments, rather than pay for future acquisitions. Oddly, controversy about commercial deaccessioning sidesteps the fact that, unless the purchase is made by another museum, objects will probably be lost to the public forever. How does that practice align with the preservation imperative museums repeatedly embrace …? Put simply: it does not."
He adds that once a work is sold, "we might as well have tossed them on a bonfire. This is a total abrogation of museological duty."
What's his answer? First, "recognize this practice for what it is and acknowledge that it contradicts a museum's commitment to preserving and caring for its collections." And then he ends up signing on to the Ellis Rule:
"Correcting the unfortunate results of unbridled commercial deaccessioning is simple. An item can be deaccessioned and kept by the museum for educational purposes. Or it can be sold or given to another museum. Everyone wins in this situation …. One museum's loss can always be another's gain."
Saturday, December 08, 2018
Settlement in the Anish Kapoor-N.R.A. Lawsuit
Monday, December 03, 2018
Saturday, December 01, 2018
"Graffiti Artists are Gaining Recognition—and Rights"
Good overview of recent developments from Bennington's K.E. Gover. An excerpt:
"Unlike traditional forms of visual art, aerosol art on building walls cannot easily be bought or sold, and they are usually understood to be ephemeral by their very nature. In one sense, this makes exterior aerosol art an uncomfortable fit for the paradigmatic VARA cases presumably intended by Congress when it passed the statute nearly thirty years ago. On the other hand, however, it highlights the interest that the 5 Pointz artists had in the preservation of their works: they could not sell them, but their ongoing presence could lead to future commissions and professional opportunities. In that sense, moral rights, despite their designation as non-economic rights, can have very real material consequences for artists. Reputation is a form of wealth."
Hail Fredonia?
SUNY Fredonia sold a painting by the Georgian painter Niko Pirosmani for $2.3 million at Sotheby's London this week.
Question: was this sale "ethical"? How should the Deaccession Police react to it?
The answer is it depends. Was the painting held in something the university called a "museum"? If so, awful, unbearable, a massive crisis, Stalin-esque.
Or was it held other than as part of a university museum -- in which case, all is fine, yawn, nothing to see here.
In this case, according to Inside Higher Ed, the painting was in something called "the Stefan Zweig Collection," which "is not part of a university museum and contains more than just artwork." So nothing to worry about, totally ethical.
You tell me how any of that makes sense as a way to evaluate these sorts of sales.
Question: was this sale "ethical"? How should the Deaccession Police react to it?
The answer is it depends. Was the painting held in something the university called a "museum"? If so, awful, unbearable, a massive crisis, Stalin-esque.
Or was it held other than as part of a university museum -- in which case, all is fine, yawn, nothing to see here.
In this case, according to Inside Higher Ed, the painting was in something called "the Stefan Zweig Collection," which "is not part of a university museum and contains more than just artwork." So nothing to worry about, totally ethical.
You tell me how any of that makes sense as a way to evaluate these sorts of sales.
"People thought maybe I was rash and should put it down to one of life’s rich experiences. But people defrauding other people, especially in the art market, should not be allowed to get away with it."
"An Artist Bought a Banksy Piece Just So He Could Destroy It"
Story here. He paid $730,000 for it and says he plans to whitewash it … and then sell it for a million dollars.
Banksy can invoke VARA to prevent this, though Guy Rub doesn't think he should be able to. And The Fashion Law blog doesn't think he will:
"The question becomes: will Banksy attempt to put a stop to English’s plan? It seems unlikely. Actually enabling English to go through with it seems like just the type of stunt and resulting publicity that Banksy is accustomed to courting. It is just barely a month after the secretive British artist saw that his famous 2006 work, Girl with Balloon, was put through a shredder just moments after it had been auctioned off for a record $1.4 million in London."
Banksy can invoke VARA to prevent this, though Guy Rub doesn't think he should be able to. And The Fashion Law blog doesn't think he will:
"The question becomes: will Banksy attempt to put a stop to English’s plan? It seems unlikely. Actually enabling English to go through with it seems like just the type of stunt and resulting publicity that Banksy is accustomed to courting. It is just barely a month after the secretive British artist saw that his famous 2006 work, Girl with Balloon, was put through a shredder just moments after it had been auctioned off for a record $1.4 million in London."
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)